Humans are ambivalent about sex because they fear death

Created 18 Aug 2012 • Last modified 1 Apr 2017

Why do strange, apparently useless sexual taboos appear in all human societies? Experiments show that people associate sexuality with animals and the body, and thus with mortality. It appears that social norms ranging from disapproval of prostitution to the ideal of romantic love exist, in part, to provide us a kind of symbolic immortality and buffer us from existential threat. There exist other potential explanations for sexual taboos, but the overall picture is not favorable to anyone who would seek to free human sexuality from artificial restrictions.

Erotophobia and ambivalence

The many exotic and bizarre manifestations of human sexuality; the cultural and religious taboos; the vows of celibacy; the often psychologically based sexual dysfunctions; the segregation of the sexes in many cultures; the veiling of women's faces and the binding of their feet; the secrecy, guilt, shame, and anxiety surrounding sexuality; and the romanticization of sexual relations in literature and real life throughout the ages all attest to the unique complexities of human sexuality. [Goldenberg, Pyszczynski, McCoy, Greenberg, & Solomon, 1999, p. 1,175]

As I discussed in the preface, people have all sorts of attitudes and societies have all sorts of rules about sexuality. Perhaps you've noticed how strange these can be.

It makes evolutionary sense that people should be disgusted by potentially dangerous activities like incest and bestiality. (The danger of incest being the investment of one's parental resources into low-fitness, inbred children, and the danger of bestiality being zoonosis and even injury, as in the famous Enumclaw horse-sex case; Sullivan, 2005). Accordingly, Fessler and Navarrete (2003) (p. 407) cite findings of such disgust in the West, the Pacific Islands, and Sub-Saharan Africa.

But why should we be frightened or disgusted by, say, masturbation or tribadism, especially if such activities do in fact have adaptive value (as was ambivalently suggested in a previous chapter), and animals, although they don't universally participate in such activities, never express aversion to them like ours? And this issue is but one part of the vast and mysterious web of rules about sexuality and (more generally) the flesh that permeate human society. Such rules are often associated with religion: Christianity, thanks to Gnosticism, tends to associate sexual purity and incorporeality with godliness, both Jewish and Islamic texts prescribe death penalties for things as innocuous as gay sex and premarital coitus, and the Kama Sutra has all kinds of odd rules for enjoying the many sexual acts it describes (Goldenberg et al., 1999). Beginning under Victorianism, secular intellectuals like physicians got into the act with pseudomedical excuses (Stearns, 2009), as by blaming masturbation for insanity. And some of the most general bodily rules are attributed to vague needs for privacy or decency: in the West and in many other societies, bathrooms are sex-segregated, farting is embarrassing, sexual and scatological references must be minimized and euphemized in polite conversation—and however acceptable nudity is in special circumstances like medical examinations, beaches, saunas, nudist colonies, athletics, and theater, it's out of the question in everyday social interaction, no matter how little the practical reasons for wearing clothing (protection from cold, sun, bugs, etc.) apply in the local environment. Finally, in the West, notice that sexuality is considered to be among the things that children need to be protected from (Arfer, 2011). Here's a great example of how nonsensical sexual taboos can appear from an outsider's perspective: Goldenberg et al. (1999), citing Powdermaker (1933), say (p. 1,174) "the Lesu of the South Pacific accept female masturbation any time a woman becomes aroused as long as she does it by pressing the heel of the right foot against her genitals; the use of one's hands for masturbation is strictly forbidden."

The most important point to be made here is that taboos and regulations about sex and the body that have no obvious function are often wildly heterogeneous between cultures but their existence is universal. There isn't a single culture without such taboos. Let me strengthen that claim a bit: there isn't a single culture without sexual taboos. The societies that are sometimes held up as examples of societies without sexual taboos, aren't. For example, Ray (2009) claims "Sweden's full of those people" who don't feel guilty about premarital sex, but most Swedes disapprove of 15-year-old girls having casual sex (Trost & Bergstrom-Walan, 2004). And Ray says "Tahiti is full of those teenagers who have sex before they're married and nobody feels guilt about it", but Tahitians zealously guard the premarital virginity of one kind of teenager: "firstborn daughters in lineages of firstborns" (Bolin, 2004). Not to mention the controversy over Margaret Mead's claims about sexuality in Samoa.

Anyway, the point is, although human societies vary widely in terms of sexual libertarianism, history recalls not a single human society that managed to be as uniformly sex-positive as bonobos. Civilization invariably contains, in a word, erotophobia. In science, the word "erotophobia" usually refers to a dimension of personality that describes the tendency to approach or avoid sexual things (Fisher, White, Byrne, & Kelley, 1988). I'm abusing the word here to refer to much larger-scale, social phenomena. While I expect that there's a meaningful relationship between these two kinds of erotophobia, personal and societal, my concern is mostly with the latter. The fact that everyone wears clothes strikes me as more in need of explanation than the fact that some people are blatantly anxious about sex.

With both erotophobia and appreciation of sexual pleasure being universal features of human societies, it's fair to say that humans, as a species, are ambivalent about sex. "Ambivalence" meaning not mere uncertainty but the coexistence of simultaneous contradictory feelings. As Davis and Whitten (1987) put it, "It is not ethnocentric to conclude that a degree of ambivalnce typifies much sexual behavior" (p. 78). A corollary is that sex-positive feminists who hope to defeat erotophobia and create a sex-positive society are taking on a much greater challenge than they may've anticipated. They're not just fighting Victorianism or Western civilization or religion. They're fighting human nature.

Terror-management theory

Speaking of human nature, let me now expound on what I see as the best available explanation for people's ambivalence about sex and the body. For the first time in this book, there's a wealth of relevant experimental evidence, so I'll be able to make some strong claims.

Theory and findings

Terror-management theory (TMT) postulates that denying personal mortality is a primary human motive (Greenberg, Solomon, & Arndt, 2008). Humans, uniquely among all animals, are intelligent enough to have a sense of self and also to understand that they as agents are certain to eventually stop existing. Thus they create and endorse ideals, philosophies, and social structures that imbue life with symbolic meaning, providing a kind of symbolic immortality. This broad idea is originally due to Ernest Becker, an anthropologist who was inspired by Otto Rank and hence by Freud, but it was first examined experimentally by Jeff Greenberg, Tom Pyszczynski, and Sheldon Solomon.

Basic TMT experiments take the form of making mortality salient to subjects assigned to the experimental group, while making some other topic salient to subjects in the control group. Possible mortality cues include having subjects describe in writing "the emotions that the thought of your own death arouses in you" or subliminally1 presenting the word "dead". Control cues may prime a totally innocuous concept, such as television, or an aversive but nonlethal concept, such as dental pain or flunking a test. Then the researchers measure subjects' adherence to or defensiveness about supposedly death-denying constructs, such as social groups or religions. Sure enough, mortality salience makes people more clannish: death-primed Christians view Christians more favorably and Jews more negatively (Greenberg et al., 1990), death-primed whites express more positive attitudes towards white racists (Greenberg, Schimel, Martens, Solomon, & Pyszcznyski, 2001), and death-primed Scots judge the English more negatively (Castano, 2004). An example of a subtler mortality-salience effect is provided by Taylor (2012), who found that mortality salience increased preference for TV shows with themes of law and justice, like Law & Order. Furthermore, among Taylor's death-primed subjects, watching an episode of Law & Order ameliorated a self-enhancing bias observed in subjects who saw no episode or an edited version of the episode in which justice was thwarted. Thus, seeing justice being done seems to comfort death anxiety, and people choose what media to consume accordingly.

So where do sex and the body come in? You would expect that mortality salience could increase defensiveness about sexual norms just as for any other social norm, as in Rosenblatt, Greenberg, Solomon, Pyszczynski, and Lyon (1989), in which death-primed municipal court judges recommended higher bonds for indicted prostitutes. The thing about the body, though, is that it is itself a reminder of mortality. The fact that our minds are so tightly bound to bodies undermines the symbolic immortality we strive for. We may then be threatened not just by illness and injury but also by pleasures of the flesh like food and sex. And the picture is further complicated by how bodies and sex can themselves take on symbolic and therefore terror-management value: think of athletes who strive for an ideal physique, or men who boast of their sexual conquests.

The complex relationship between death and sex in the human mind has been examined primarily by Jamie Goldenberg. To begin with, Study 1 of Goldenberg et al. (1999) found that mortality salience made the "physical aspects" of sex less appealing, in that death-primed subjects gave lower appeal ratings to experiences during sex such as "Having an orgasm" and "Feeling my partner's sweat on my body". Ratings for the "romantic aspects" of sex, like "Blending of selves" and "Expressing love for my partner", were unchanged. Conversely, in Study 2, priming subjects with physical but not romantic aspects increased the accessibility of death (i.e., how readily death-related knowledge was brought to mind), as measured by how subjects filled in word fragments such as "C O F F _ _" that had death-related and non–death-related solutions ("coffin" versus "coffee"). So it appears that we associate sex with death, and this association is what makes sex potentially unsettling. The significance of the romanticization of sex was best demonstrated by Study 3, which showed that additionally priming subjects with the concept of romantic love removes the increase in death accessibility brought about by a sex prime. So romance can act as a means of whitewashing sexuality: as Goldenberg et al. put it (p. 1,176), "Romantic love transforms sex from an animal act to a symbolic human experience, thereby making it a highly meaningful part of one's cultural worldview and obscuring its threatening link to mortality."

A catch of the effects just described is that they were found only in people relatively high in neuroticism, one of the Big Five personality traits. There are plausible theoretical reasons for this, such as neuroticism either causing or being caused by difficulty with terror management. But the plausibility of TMT as an explanation for large-scale features of human society suffers, since we'd expect that low-neuroticism people have a lot of influence on social norms, too. Fortunately, Goldenberg, Cox, Pyszczynski, Greenberg, and Solomon (2002) were able to find a reduction of the appeal of the physical aspects of sex that wasn't influenced by neuroticism, with the help of an additional manipulation: having subjects read an essay that emphasized the similarity of humans to other animals (by saying things like "the boundary between humans and animals is not as great as most people think"). The idea is that maintaining an ideological distinction between humans and animals is another way to defend against the mortality salience of corporeality. When this defense is undermined, even low-neuroticism people can be intimidated by the connection between lust and death.

To extend this thinking to bodily things other than sex, consider Goldenberg et al. (2006). Again, the effects of interest were found only in high-neuroticism people. In Study 2, death-primed subjects spent less time using a foot massager. In Study 1, death-primed subjects lasted for a shorter time in the cold-pressor task, that is, the keeping-your-hand-in-ice-water task, which has a long history of use in experimental psychology as a pain stimulus; in this study, however, subjects "were told that different individuals find the experience 'exhilarating, uncomfortable, pleasurable, or unpleasant.'". The value of this paper is that the dependent measures concern tactile sensations, one pleasurable and one painful, that aren't related to sex and to which few social norms apply.

As an example of how even the physical aspects of sex can manage terror, consider Study 2 of Goldenberg, McCoy, Pyszczynski, Greenberg, and Solomon (2000). Subjects high on a measure of "body esteem" (how positively they viewed their appearance, strength, sensations, etc.) found the physical aspects of sex more appealing after a death prime. (Neuroticism wasn't measured.)

Finally, McCallum and McGlone (2011) examined a perhaps more down-to-earth dependent variable: euphemism. Subjects had to write descriptions of nine photographs, supposedly for another subject who would try to answer questions about each image using only the description. Between subjects, the seventh image was randomly assigned to be a picture of dogs urinating, defecating, or copulating. Death-primed subjects were more likely to describe these actions euphemistically.

The moral of the above

That was a lot to digest, so, to review and synthesize: sex, insofar as it is fleshly and creaturely, can be upsetting by its association with mortality. To defend against these mortality concerns, we can distance ourselves from them by euphemizing bodily functions or thinking of ourselves as distinct from animals, or we can whitewash sexuality with socially valued notions like romantic love, or we can try to squeeze some symbolic immortality out of the body itself. While these phenomena are thoroughly entangled with social norms in practice, the core death–body link seems not to require social norms for its existence.

Is terror management responsible for real-life erotophobia?

Altogether, this is a gorgeous theoretical package. The universality of mortality explains the universality of erotophobia, and the diversity of ways in which terror can be managed explains the diversity of sexual rules. The biggest gap is a problem inherent to any attempt to use experimental psychology to explain social trends: external validity. Is the congruence between the laboratory findings of TMT and real-world erotophobia enlightening or misleading? To give a concrete example: we know that sex can arouse mortality concerns, but are mortality concerns really part of why we wear clothes in practice? Another: we know that romance can ease mortality concerns aroused by sexuality, but is this effect really part of why romance is valued to begin with? Such hypotheses about cause and effect in societies as wholes are difficult to test observationally and practically impossible to test experimentally. (Thinking about these things makes one a bit more sympathetic to the methods of sociology, doesn't it? Sociologists seek answers to some very hard questions.) So until some very ambitious studies are run, I have no better answer to such questions than the following: affirmative answers are most consistent with TMT, which is supported by experiment.

Is terror management bad?

It's stupid that we go to such lengths to deny the inevitable. Becker himself argued that the denial of death is responsible for much of the evil in the world: war between ideological factions, for example, may arise because one ideology challenges the soundness of another (e.g., Christian and Islamic beliefs contradict each other) and thus undermines it as a source of symbolic immortality. Frankly, TMT is itself terrifying. However, we should not assume that all behavior that happens to be motivated by mortality concerns is bad. With respect to sex, we'll see in the chapters to come why wariness of human sexuality may be justifiable, and even why it might be wise to dress modestly.

Still, it is reasonable to ask what we can do about whichever aspects of erotophobia we've decided are harmful. (Indeed, as I see it, the primary value of knowing the causes of erotophobia is to help control erotophobia.) I've argued that TMT implies erotophobia in general cannot be vanquished without changing human nature itself. But the diversity we've seen in how people manage terror suggests that, by means of clever social engineering, we may be able to replace people's terror-management strategies with more useful ones, which focus on the actual dangers of sexuality without spilling over into excessive sex-negativity. (For example, imagine if people felt condoms and consent were what made sex palatable.) Obviously, this is easier said than done.

More broadly, I hope you agree that a certain healthy fear of death is a good thing. If we value anything we can do while we're alive, we should value life. Not to mention that terror management may be a key ingredient of human ambition and achievement. Goodness knows that I'm trying to get some symbolic immortality out of doing science—that awareness of my own finitude is what motivates me to value my own experiences less than what happens to humanity as a whole. So it's possible to fly from death more prosocially than Voldemort, the Harry Potter villain who cast evil spells in the pursuit of immortality.

A final caveat: TMT isn't everything

It has sometimes been suggested that mortality salience is not merely one basic human motive among many, but the most important one, or even the most fundamental one, from which all behavior originates. For example, Greenberg et al. (2008) entertain the notion (although they cite it to Yalom, 1980) that "all psychopathology is (at least in part) the result of ineffective terror management" (p. 128).

I don't like this line of thinking one bit. It smacks of Freud; it's one way that TMT's origin in Becker, a non-scientist, may keep it from developing properly. TMT is a big, powerful theory, but there's hardly evidence that it's equipped to be psychology's theory of everything. Nor should any sane person expect such evidence to arise. One simple reason why: to return to the theme of Goldenberg et al. (2002), human behavior is in many substantial ways similar to the behavior of other animals, but TMT doesn't apply to animals.

Alternative explanations

Let's discuss some candidate alternative causes of erotophobia, not least because terror management may not be the only cause.

My perception is that most writers put the blame for erotophobia on some aspect of culture, such as religion. Along these lines, Fisher et al. (1988) say about erotophobia-the-personality-dimension, "because sexual behavior is inherently rewarding, erotophilia [i.e., low erotophobia] would presumably be the norm were it not for the effects of sex-related punishment" (p. 134). I don't doubt that culture has all kinds of influences on individuals' sexual attitudes, as implied by some of the TMT research. However, the universality of erotophobia raises the question of why so many human cultures happened to become erotophobic before they interacted. So culture isn't an acceptable ultimate explanation.

A disgust theory

One could try to explain erotophobia in terms of disgust. Sex is disgusting because it's unclean. Besides sex being truly unhygenic because of the transmission of bodily fluids like sweat, saliva, and semen, we may mentally associate sex with excretion because the penis excretes urine, the anus excretes feces, and the vagina excretes menses. But we need to overcome this disgust to have sex, so (it appears) evolution has arranged for sexual arousal to dampen disgust reactions, or at least disgust reactions towards sexual stimuli (Stevenson, Case, & Oaten, 2011, observed this in men and Borg & de Jong, 2012, observed it in women). So the overall prediction is that we'll find sexual things disgusting whenever we don't find them arousing. If we combine this line of thinking with the observation I belabored in the chapter on preferences, namely, that sexual preferences are idiosyncratic, it follows that what we find sexually disguting—our "sexual antipreferences", as it were—should be similarly idiosyncratic. Hypothesize some way by which particular sexual antipreferences could (a) dominate a culture (the same way that some sexual preferences, like a preference for large breasts, dominate cultures) and (b) generalize to negative reactions other than disgust (such as fear), and you have a process for generating kinds of erotophobia as weird as the ones we observe.

I think that this idea is original. There are no direct tests of it. But my reading of the literature (see appendix: http://arfer.net/w/esa/disgust-theory) is that support for it is mixed. It doesn't seem equipped to replace TMT any time soon.

Others

I've seen reasonable theories for many classes of the social norms that I've characterized as erotophobic. To wit:

  • When resources are scarce, as they have been in most societies, reproduction is risky. If there's too many mouths to feed, someone will starve. Without good contraceptives, regulating coitus is the only reliable way to regulate reproduction. (This is the line of thinking favored by Stearns, 2009.)
  • Similarly, one way to avoid STDs is to avoid sex.
  • In a society in which paternity is important (e.g., because possessions are inherited patrilineally), paternity has to be known. And the only way to keep track of paternity without paternity testing is to regulate who copulates with whom.
  • More generally, one way people might reinforce their social dominance over other people (e.g., men over women, or clergy over laity) is to make the latter follow a lot of unpleasant or degrading rules.
  • People may be partly aware of the ways in which sexual stimuli and feelings can have undesirable influences on human behavior (again, see the chapters to come). Rules like nudity bans could be an attempt to minimize such harm. (See DeForest, 2011, for a humorous exposition of this idea.)

While any number of these theories may be right, they're not enough, even as a package. I mean, I can imagine how functional norms, as people lost sight of their purpose over time, could grow into monsters. For example, rules that were intended or that memetically evolved to keep sexual feelings from interfering with cognition may have given birth to a less pragmatic anxiety about sexuality that in turn created Victorianism, even though extreme anxiety about sexuality is a solution worse than the problem. What these theories can't explain, and where TMT shines, is that regulations about sexuality having no obvious function are universal, but obvious fully general anxiety about sexuality is not. (If the horny nude Marquesan girls who swam out to greet sailors (Bolin, 2004) were anxious about sexuality, they sure as heck didn't know it.) The regulations imply some kind of crazy unconscious inconsistent-yet-fully-general anxiety about sexuality, which only TMT (and perhaps the disgust theory) can explain. Also, these theories don't enjoy the experimental support of TMT.

References

Arfer, K. B. (2011). Vicarious restraint. Retrieved from http://arfer.net/w/vicarious-restraint

Bolin, A. (2004). French Polynesia. In R. T. Francoeur & R. J. Noonan (Eds.), The Continuum complete international encyclopedia of sexuality. New York, NY: Continuum. Retrieved from https://kinseyinstitute.org/pdf/ccies-frenchpolynesia.pdf

Borg, C., & de Jong, P. J. (2012). Feelings of disgust and disgust-induced avoidance weaken following induced sexual arousal in women. PLOS ONE. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0044111

Castano, E. (2004). In case of death, cling to the ingroup. European Journal of Social Psychology, 34, 375–384. doi:10.1002/ejsp.211

Davis, D. L., & Whitten, R. G. (1987). The cross-cultural study of human sexuality. Annual Review of Anthropology, 16(1), 69–98. doi:10.1146/annurev.an.16.100187.000441

DeForest, C. E. (2011, March 24). drzowie comments on ELI5: Why do we wear clothes/Are ashamed to be naked? Retrieved from https://www.reddit.com/r/explainlikeimfive/comments/rbosq/x/c44ihs6

Fessler, D. M. T., & Navarrete, C. D. (2003). Domain-specific variation in disgust sensitivity across the menstrual cycle. Evolution and Human Behavior, 24(6), 406–417. doi:10.1016/S1090-5138(03)00054-0

Fisher, W. A., White, L. A., Byrne, D., & Kelley, K. (1988). Erotophobia-erotophilia as a dimension of personality. Journal of Sex Research, 25(1), 123–151. doi:10.1080/00224498809551448

Goldenberg, J. L., Cox, C. R., Pyszczynski, T., Greenberg, J., & Solomon, S. (2002). Understanding human ambivalence about sex: The effects of stripping sex of meaning. Journal of Sex Research, 39(4), 310–320. doi:10.1080/00224490209552155

Goldenberg, J. L., Hart, J., Pyszczynski, T., Warnica, G. M., Landau, M., & Thomas, L. (2006). Ambivalence toward the body: Death, neuroticism, and the flight from physical sensation. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 32(9), 1264–1277. doi:10.1177/0146167206289505

Goldenberg, J. L., McCoy, S. K., Pyszczynski, T., Greenberg, J., & Solomon, S. (2000). The body as a source of self-esteem: The effect of mortality salience on identification with one's body, interest in sex, and appearance monitoring. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 79(1), 118–130. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.79.1.118

Goldenberg, J. L., Pyszczynski, T., McCoy, S. K., Greenberg, J., & Solomon, S. (1999). Death, sex, love, and neuroticism: Why is sex such a problem? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 77(6), 1173–1187. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.77.6.1173

Greenberg, J., Pyszczynski, T., Solomon, S., Rosenblatt, A., Veeder, M., Kirkland, S., & Lyon, D. (1990). Evidence for terror management theory II: The effects of mortality salience on reactions to those who threaten or bolster the cultural worldview. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 58(2), 308–318. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.58.2.308

Greenberg, J., Schimel, J., Martens, A., Solomon, S., & Pyszcznyski, T. (2001). Sympathy for the devil: Evidence that reminding Whites of their mortality promotes more favorable reactions to White racists. Motivation and Emotion, 25, 113–133. doi:10.1023/A:1010613909207

Greenberg, J., Solomon, S., & Arndt, J. (2008). A basic but uniquely human motivation: Terror management theory. In J. Y. Shah & W. L. Gardner (Eds.), Handbook of motivation science (pp. 114–134). New York, NY: The Guilford Press.

Karremans, J. C., Stroebe, W., & Claus, J. (2006). Beyond Vicary's fantasies: The impact of subliminal priming and brand choice. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 42, 792–798. doi:10.1016/j.jesp.2005.12.002

McCallum, N. L., & McGlone, M. S. (2011). Death be not profane: Mortality salience and euphemism use. Western Journal of Communication, 75(5), 565–584. doi:10.1080/10570314.2011.608405

Powdermaker, H. (1933). Life in Lesu. New York, NY: Norton.

Pratkanis, A. R. (1992). The cargo-cult science of subliminal persuasion. Skeptical Inquirer, 16. Retrieved from http://www.csicop.org/si/show/cargo-cult_science_of_subliminal_persuasion

Ray, D. W. (2009, May 11). God Virus Part 8: The Sexual Guilt Cycle [Video file]. Retrieved from http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=SLsNZ8vk1Xs

Rosenblatt, A., Greenberg, J., Solomon, S., Pyszczynski, T., & Lyon, D. (1989). Evidence for terror management theory: I. The effects of mortality salience on reactions to those who violate or uphold cultural values. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 57(4), 681–690. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.57.4.681

Stearns, P. N. (2009). Sexuality in world history. London, England: Routledge. ISBN 0-203-88032-3.

Stevenson, R. J., Case, T. I., & Oaten, M. J. (2011). Effect of self-reported sexual arousal on responses to sex-related and non-sex-related disgust cues. Archives of Sexual Behavior, 40(1), 79–85. doi:10.1007/s10508-009-9529-z

Sullivan, J. (2005, July 15). Enumclaw-area animal-sex case investigated. The Seattle Times. Retrieved from http://www.seattletimes.com/seattle-news/enumclaw-area-animal-sex-case-investigated

Taylor, L. D. (2012). Death and television: Terror management theory and themes of law and justice on television. Death Studies, 36(4), 340–359. doi:10.1080/07481187.2011.553343

Trost, J. E., & Bergstrom-Walan, M.-B. (2004). Sweden. In R. T. Francoeur & R. J. Noonan (Eds.), The Continuum complete international encyclopedia of sexuality. New York, NY: Continuum. Retrieved from https://kinseyinstitute.org/pdf/ccies-sweden.pdf

Yalom, I. D. (1980). Existential psychotherapy. New York, NY: Basic Books. ISBN 0465021476.

Notes

1

Yes, surprisingly enough, subliminal messages can actually work. An example outside of TMT: Karremans, Stroebe, and Claus (2006) got subliminal presentation of the phrase "Lipton Ice" to increase preference for Lipton Ice over mineral water, at least for thirsty subjects. So perhaps the legend of James Vicary (Pratkanis, 1992) was, as a mathematician would say, morally true, after all.